While writing my first novel, Lightbearer, one that encompassed the
improbable span of eternity,it was necessary to think about the world without
preconception—creation, sexuality,desire, and consciousness--imagining them,
inasmuch as possible, as they would appear to those who were not influenced by
successive layers of historical interpretation, received wisdom or the cultural
norms of the present. The old verities had to be reset to zero.
Scientific discovery has the power to reset our understanding of the world also.
Indeed biochemistry and neuroscience have made discoveries that
recontextualize, even overturn, our past understanding of human emotion and
attachment. That is to say, if there are hormones that produce or are
produced upon the apprehension of love, then such understandings might tend to
demythologize the ‘divine’ emotion, strip it of a religious moral imperative:
love thy neighbor as thyself. Yet, love need not lose its appeal or
prominence in the process, neither to be viewed on one hand as a construct,
some bourgeois social convention that requires ironic quotations around it, nor
as the greatest commandment.
Even if love came about by accident, human connection has a life, a
practical essence, which operates outside the modes dictated by religion, the
theoretical deconstructions of modernism, or the mere biologically programmed
response. We continue to ratify love in living no matter what religionists
proscribe, and no matter how much the cynics scoff. More than a few existential
philosophers and not a few novelists have had to go home and answer to their
wives and lovers after proclaiming that life is a meaningless accident and love
a mindless biological impulse designed to trick us into reproducing. And
in the era of same sex marriage, gays and lesbians will be excused if they fail
to believe religionists who say their love either does not exist or is a
mistake. When it comes to love and living in general, one needs to steel
oneself with a certain moral independence to act freely and live
creatively.
For me, this moral independence is the ground fiction seeks to claim as its
territory. So even while writing, or re-writing, the central Judeo-Christian
story found in scripture, in imagining the beginning and the end of all things,
it was as essential to fully engage theological questions inherent in that
narrative frame as it was to make space for the science that prevails today in
the re-examination of such beginnings and endings, and possible spaces in
between. The idea was to let them fight it out, qualify and inform each
other. For, in Lightbearer, even God complies with the physics of the
Second Coming: being close enough to be seen by all, means not being seen
by all at once, rather letting
Parousia roll
from place to place across the land. Anything the novel can imagine, like God
himself, it can contain for the sake of experimental knowledge. This is
neither a scientific knowing, nor a religious kind, but a testing of human
nature that is predictive all the same. It may be informed, like love, by
science and religion but it is not constrained by either in its
knowledge-seeking. The idea of being able to examine different modes of
experience alternatively or concurrently, this kind of fighting it out, seems
to be a pluralistic notion. An art form you might expect to flourish in a
secular society.
In
The Broken
Estate (2004), James Wood came out as a champion of the novel’s secularity
and stated that what was most secular about the novel was our ability to choose
to believe or not believe in the world of a work of fiction, and that this
belief was a provisional,
as if, belief:
"Nevertheless, the reality of fiction must also
draw its power from the reality of the world. The real, in fiction,
is always a matter of belief, and is therefore a kind of discretionary
magic: it is a magic whose existence it is up to us, as readers, to validate and
confirm. It is this reason that many readers dislike actual magic or fantasy in
novels…Fiction demands belief from us, and that is demanding partly because we can
choose not to believe. However, magic—improbable occurrences, ghosts, coincidences—dismantles
belief, forcing on us miracles which, because
they
are beyond belief, we cannot choose not to believe. This is why almost
all fiction
is not magical, and why the great writers of magical tales are so densely realistic.
…This is surely the true secularism of fiction—why,
despite being a kind of
magic, it is actually the enemy of
superstition, the slayer of religions, the scrutineer
of falsity. Fiction moves in the shadow of doubt, knows itself to be a true lie, knows
that at any moment it might fail to make its case. Belief in fiction is always belief
“as if.” Our belief is itself metaphorical—it only
resembles actual belief, and is therefore
never wholly belief."
Wood’s recognition of provisional belief in the novel rings true in a very
common sense way. It was Coleridge after all who coined the phrase
“willing suspension of disbelief” nearly two hundred years ago, though he had
in mind the kind of fantastic tales Wood finds problematic. In 1817
Coleridge was recalling his collaboration with Wordsworth on
Lyric Ballads two
decades earlier, and this work came at the end of a century that had seen a
sharp decline in belief in the supernatural:
"... It was
agreed, that my endeavours should be directed to persons and characters supernatural, or at least romantic, yet so as to transfer
from our inward nature a human
interest and a semblance of truth sufficient to procure for these shadows of
imagination that willing
suspension of disbelief for the moment, which constitutes poetic faith. Mr. Wordsworth on
the other hand was to propose to himself as his
object, to give the charm of novelty
to things of every day, and to excite a feeling
analogous to the supernatural, by
awakening the mind's attention from the lethargy of
custom, and directing it to the loveliness and the wonders of the world
before
us ..."
Coleridge’s notion of suspending disbelief as poetic faith seems a necessary
post-Enlightenment strategy for resuscitating the “shadows of imagination” that
had languished in the preceding century, requiring an attention to “human
interest and a semblance of truth” on the writer’s part (being true to human
nature and the psyche as much as to the“density of realism” Wood describes),
and “suspension of disbelief for the moment” on the reader’s part.
Nevertheless, this attitude seems necessary for the appreciation of any
performance involving artifice, from a magic show, a play, or a two dimensional
movie on a screen, certainly to anything enclosed between two covers, and,
whether on the page or the stage, this approach to narrative and drama began
long before the reign of secularism. Coleridge is merely one of the
literary spirits responsible for reviving the tradition of supernatural
manifestation that two centuries later seems again dubious to Wood. It
has come in and out of fashion before. Yet today, in popular literature,
fantasy has never enjoyed a more robust place, while in the halls of academia
there has been much written, however hyperbolic, about the death of literary
realism or, at least, about the death of conventional notions of “the real”.
Some of it is a direct response to Wood’s ideas.
Wood may have it wrong, at least in part, when he asserts that many dislike
the magical or supernatural in fiction because they“cannot choose not to
believe” in it. Take, for instance, a production of Hamlet in Elizabethan
England (a time when belief in witches and ghosts would not raise as many
eyebrows as it might today) and the ghost of Hamlet’s father in particular.
Just because you believe in ghosts as actual phenomena doesn’t mean you believe
that you are seeing an actual ghost on the stage. A suspension of
disbelief is required regardless of whether you believe in ghosts or not, for
the purposes and moment of the drama before you. You might be more
inclined to feel a shiver of real haunting if the actor portraying Hamlet
appeared shaken enough that you felt his fear and wonder. What also makes the
ghost believable is that the ghost is a metaphor for a more substantial,
everyday concern in monarchical Elizabethan society: a murdered king and
a usurped throne. That knowledge for Hamlet is the real ghost, it truly
haunts him, and so the ghost is almost more poignant if you don’t believe in
ghosts, because it plays off that unbelief to remind us how irreversible death
is: only Hamlet, not the dead king, can avenge that crime.
The fact that we don’t believe in actual ghosts and yet can feel the shiver
of what it would be
like
to see a ghost does not convert us to believing in ghosts after seeing Hamlet.
By the same reasoning, if we believe in actual ghosts but refuse to believe in
that ghost on the stage (if only because he bumped into a prop and spoiled the
notion of his immateriality) it will not slay our belief in ghosts in real
life. Wood’s objection to the supernatural is canceled out, then, because not
only is the operative belief in fiction
as if but the
doubt we experience also is
as if. For,
how can we experience real doubt about a fictional ghost? Wood’s own
statement about belief, then, is fully applicable to doubt: Our
doubt is itself metaphorical—it only
resembles actual
doubt, and is therefore never wholly doubt. Now, metaphoric doubt can be
overcome with a great performance, just as metaphoric belief in even an
ordinary action can be undone by an actor’s clumsiness. Wood does not
explicitly acknowledge the nature of fictional doubt, in fact, privileges doubt
over belief by assuming that the doubt we experience reading fiction is real
doubt, while the belief we experience reading fiction is a most tenuous,
provisional belief. We no more apply true skepticism in the reading of
fiction than we do when listening to the telling of a dream. For once
inside the novel, the operative mode is metaphoric from alpha to omega.
Contrary to Wood’s assertion that the presence of the magical takes away our
freedom to refuse belief, I think it possible that metaphoric assent to
something that does not exist may actually restore (even a skeptic’s) freedom
to recover belief
for
the moment. All we have to do is reverse Wood’s premise to neutralize
it. Does not an atheist, like Wood, forego the freedom of believing in
the supernatural? If the facts of the natural world determine Wood’s
atheism, then he does not have a choice to believe in the supernal (if he
rejects god, he is a believer in disguise). His atheism, as fact, has
denied him a certain freedom: belief in the supernal. Does
not being limited to believing only in the real, or natural, in fiction, also
make us unable to choose to believe in the impossible in that fiction? The last
phrase generates the same predicament as Wood’s double negative formulation,
“we cannot choose not to believe.” These are reversible propositions:
the
impossible,
because it is beyond belief and makes us unable to choose to doubt it, deprives
us our freedom (Wood’s proposal); or, the
possible,because
it is the basis of reality and makes us unable to choose not to accept it,
deprives us our freedom (my proposal). If you squint one eye or the
other, doubt or belief can be seen as equal hindrances to freedom, even if both
of these propositions are overstated in the acknowledged play world of fiction.
I would grant there are readers who dislike actual magic in novels because
it is simply beyond belief, not because in some abstract way it impinges on
their freedom to express doubt. In a way, the refusal of the magical
shows an inclination to believe over an inclination to doubt, in that a secular
person is not looking to secure room for doubt in denying the magical, but to
make a secure space for the “real” they may believe in. From another
angle, it could be said that many secularists want to deal only in secular
terms, like vendors who deal only in their own national currency. Indeed, to
such readers, the magical may be as useless, as impractical, as presenting
Deutche Marks at a McDonald’s in Topeka, Kansas. This impasse with the
miraculous or magical, though, expresses the deeper need to keep the domains of
the religious/supernal and the secular/common separate.
This anxiety exists because often such “readers of reality” have had to come
through much struggle to achieve this separation and thus cannot easily or
comfortably endure its breaching. It is similar to the way some gay readers of
my novel,
Lightbearer,
find it so objectionable. For, it is both incomprehensible and
an outrage to their sense of justice that a gay man would write a novel that
frames the origins of same sex love within a Biblical narrative that is used to
condemn it, rather than in a secular liberation context. It must seem to
them like the Israelites returning to Egypt after having been freed. For
me though, the impulse of gays to submerse in urban subcultures, liberation in
isolation, had at some point become escapism rather than true liberation.
Security maintained by separation. A different set of chains.The parallel
between atheism and gay experience can be drawn because in America, for many
people with high profile public lives, coming out of the closet as atheist is
as potentially risky, if not more so, than coming out as gay. So, in this
milieu of sharp division between interior life and public profession, there is
a keen awareness of the security of these boundaries. The supernatural or
magical in novels is yet another laden symbolic crossing of planes and
boundaries between the religious and secular that constitutes a violation (a
novelistic merger of church and state if you will), more about the incursion
into existential territory than the deprivation of a freedom to believe or
doubt.
AmardeepSingh in his 2006 critical volume
Literary
Secularism:Religion and Modernity in Twentieth-Century Fiction observes
this separation anxiety in the way Wood is critical of the late 19
th
century secularization of religion: “Wood prefers writers to be either openly
religious or openly atheist, and expresses impatience with those who occupy the
in-between space of Matthew Arnold’s ‘religion of culture’.”
This crossing of planes comes up in my novel,
Lightbearer, when
Virgil Caldera is trying to negotiate his departure from his church. It
is not just a matter of not showing up on Sabbath for services, it is a matter
of abandoning belief. In the scene below, Vigil is dining with his
would-be lover, Joe Coseia, who happens to be Lucifer in human disguise.
The problem for Virgil is that he has received not only a vision from God, but
a pendant, an artifact of divine revelation, that he finds impossible to
rationalize away:
“I
can’t just turn off my memory. It’s not like before. I’ve seen him.
I know he’s real. He
is coming.”
“You’re serious.”
“Of course.” Virgil stabbed a falafel ball with his fork.
“I have to admit I’d be a much better devil’s advocate if I hadn’t seen you
levitate out of a church pew. It’s second nature for a skeptic to
automatically discount the presence of miracles, or at least, if you allow for
some unexplainable events, to argue alternative explanations for them.
It’s a live and let live situation. I know people who claim to have seen
ghosts and I don’t disbelieve them—I believe they believe they have—yet I have
never seen one…It’s not real to me. I can accept the possibility of a
spirit world, but I don’t claim to understand it, and I don’t seek it out.
It has nothing whatsoever to do with me; we’re like objects on parallel planes
that never intersect. And I suspect it is only real to those who live on
that plane of belief.”
“But you saw me levitate; the planes have crossed. You can’t pretend it
has nothing to do with you now.”
Later in the argument, Lucifer resorts to other rationalizations:
“…Now here’s what I think. After you let loose on my body, you’ll never
have another vision. God won’t bother you again. And it won’t be
long before you’ll wonder what on earth you were ever thinking.”
“What about the pendant?”
“It’s just an object when you separate it from your system of eschatology.”
“Like an out-of-place object?”
“Exactly,” Joe said, pointing his fork to dot his exclamation.
…”And what if he does come back?”
“Ninety-nine generations have failed before you,” Joe said, signaling the
waiter. “Even if everything you believe is true, there’s every chance
your generation will also fail. Have a little faith.”
Here the tables are turned on rationalism by an irrefutable sign, an
unexplainable object and Virgil’s levitation from a church pew before an entire
congregation. Skepticism is on the run. Never mind that Lucifer is
hiding his supernatural identity and knows that Virgil’s seduction may well
delay the Archangel’s promised return. In the face of an indisputable
miracle, Lucifer’s best devil’s advocate is an unconvincing attempt to straddle
and rationalize this difficult boundary between fundamental belief and rational
secularism by a soft live and let live separation of existential planes.
It pragmatically delays the taking of a stand on the supernal, reproducing in
us Wood's impatience and discomfort. For when it comes to miracles in
fiction, Wood would rather the planes did not cross either. Just as
the tangible miracle makes it difficult for Virgil to abandon belief, so the
absence of miracles makes it difficult for Wood to abandon his unbelief.
Either way it’s hard to abandon a fact. Because once a miracle becomes a
fact, science yields its authority by being unable to explain that fact, while
faith dissolves into a kind of science by its very confirmation as fact.
There is good reason then for both the believer and unbeliever to be nervous
about the miraculous, even if the believer is naïve about the reasons. At
the heart, then, of this difficulty of crossing planes between the religious
and secular is the fear that they may undo each other. That in some
hybrid or mitigated form they will lose the strength and efficacy of real
conviction. Thus, Wood’s harsh words for the soft secularized religion of the
late 19
th century in his essay “The Broken Estate”:
"But, the moment
at which Jesus became a hero of a novel, of a ‘prose poem’, he
also became
fictional. The old estate broke. Jesus lost his divinity, became
only an
inspiring fantasist. We may wonder what use Jesus is if he is a figure no
different
from Socrates on the one hand and Daniel Deronda on the other. Why should we heed his
difficult words, what is the flavor of his command once the taste for his
authority has evaporated? Secularists perhaps relish that point in intellectual history
at which Christianity loses its theological prestige and begins
to
fall into the secular ranks. Yet, intellectually, a new pettiness was the
first
replacement of the old, divine
Jesus, and it is hard not to lament the passing of actual belief when it is replaced with
only a futile poetry. Christianity was not, of course
shoveled away, it was coaxed into sleep by nurses who mistakenly
thought that they were
healing it. Indeed, it might be said that in the last forty years of the nineteenth century, until
Nietzsche’s decisively canceling work began to dominate,
the feeblest evasions and weakmindedness passed for theological thinking.
Ernest Renan and Matthew Arnold are the chief nurses of the sleep of nineteenth-century
Europe and in their work one finds much false medicine."
Singh uses this quote, and his commentary on it below is much to the point:
"For Wood, the
true tragedy is not Nietzsche’s rejection of God (and of Jesus), but the secularization of the Biblical narrative, such that
it becomes merely another kind
of novel. We see the fulfillment of the phrasing in the earlier quote
about fiction
as the “slayer” of religion. For Wood, the novel destroys strong belief
as a matter of form, by
introducing the option of the provisional, non-committal type of belief that
is typical of a reader’s approach to a Dickens novel. Once that way of
reading—which is also a way of being—comes to
dominate, it subsumes all other
kinds of narrative."
But is Wood right? My ghost analogy above illustrates the way that
these two modes of belief and of reading narratives continue to coexist and
compete. Religion continues to be viable in Western societies and
dominant in many Eastern ones , even in democratic India where the novel is
also vibrantly alive. Despite a secular government in the United States,
God’s name is still on the money and an openly atheist president is yet
unelectable. It is paradoxical, but essential, that secularism, which
gives rise to novelistic freedom, also gives rise to religious freedom. It’s
the key to the true secularism of the novel. For it is only in a secular
state that religious freedom can flourish (atheism enjoys protection under that
banner as well). Otherwise, what you have, and what had existed in the
West at least as far back as Rome, is state religion. The enforcement of divine
authority on earth. When the Soviet state tried to banish God, it failed at
being truly secular; for in disallowing religion, it set up the secular state
as the state religion.
Surely, one of the successes of modern secular states is the granting of
broad religious freedoms (the separation of church and state). In such
societies it is not surprising that the novel’s secular whole will reflect that
very pluralism in its pages. That is not to say there aren’t droves of novelists
who reject religion, and some even who find fault with secular humanism too
(one thinks of Thomas Bernhard, who doesn’t breathe the name of god at all in
Old Masters, but
rails ceaselessly against modern sentimentality in just about every art form). Bernhard
may refer disparagingly to Catholicism, but only as a human institution, not as
a divine agency. His novels may be the best example of what a “hard” secularism
looks like in a novel. God is not banished. God is not even an
absence, does not occupy even an inch of Kierkegaardian negative space, and yet
the subjective tyranny that rules there is a kind of God unto itself, because
it rejects almost everything in its wake, including the mode of reason in its
critique of society. It cares not if you agree or disagree.
Thus saith the Lord
is replaced by
thus
said Wortheimer, or
Reger said yesterday
at the Künsthistoriches Museum for that matter.Yet, in rejecting what it
does regard (secular society and human institutions) without recourse to its
standard means of regarding itself (through reasoned critique), it may be seen
as anti-secular. Like long, looping suicide notes to the
world, Bernhard's narratives posture in a subjective disengagement, a
mania that seems anti-pluralistic in its refusal to persuade and also in its
super-iteration--from
Gargoyles (1963)
to
Extinction (1986)--of
a single fictional style, narrative frame and story in every novel. There is
always one thing that escapes rejection, one thing that retains quality or
value, in a Bernhard novel. In
The Loser it is
Glenn Gould’s
Goldberg
Variations. In
Old Masters it is
Tintoretto’s
White
Bearded Man. As delightful as Bernhard’s narrators are despite themselves,
their monism smacks of a theology of the self that may be the ultimate pitfall
of a “hard” fundamental secularism.
It is no stretch to say authors of serious literary novels have an
overwhelmingly secular outlook, as Singh also notes at the outset of his
study.Yet, far from excluding religion from the novel, secularism has ensured
religious inclusion, if only because so many secular authors have unfinished
business with religion. In principle, so long as the novel is pluralistic
and free it never will be a “hard secular” art form, never free of religious
influence. For free religious belief, in various ways, informs the sphere
of its practice. Scripture alone, the Bible in Western tradition, is a
rich literary source of metaphor and carries with it a trail of historical and
cultural associations that are not easily abandoned. Yet, it is the
conflict that arises so often with religion’s inclusion, the uncomfortable
subway car ride of atheists, fundamentalists, nominal believers and New Age
appropriators, jostling elbow to elbow at rush hour, that makes the novel most
secular. That is, the intransigence of the plural and the inclusion
of conflict in the novel, this very essence of freedom in
the text,
commends it as a secular bastion. It is worth noting, and not so
surprising, that Wood, the critic, locates the
novel’s most secular
aspect in the non-commital attitude of the
reader toward the
text, rather than finding it in the texts themselves as Singh does.
Being free and human in every detail, novels do not deny access to religion
in their inquiry, the way science or orthodox religion must prohibit other
forms of inquiry in their domains to maintain their purity. The trying of
religion is essential to fiction’s experiment. The pervasiveness and
persistence of religious ideas and values in world culture means it is
unavoidable in life, and so we should expect it to appear in our novels.
The novel, then, if it is a secular form of human knowledge-seeking, thrives on
dissent (especially since novelists are the ones picking the fights), and
limits its own secular power to work out these conflicts even if it does so
ambivalently. After all, allowing characters of diverse beliefs into a
novel requires the same loosening of artistic control that allows characters to
speak freely in their distinctive voices in the first place, rather than just
being mouthpieces for the author’s opinions. How these experiments turn out
(the knowledge of the end) and why they matter is what the novel attempts to
get right. If it fails to answer the great questions, at least it is
asking the questions we want answered, and, as it moves from the
particular life to the general metaphor of human experience, it promises, if it
is bold fiction, to make an educated guess about how its own fictional world,
if not the actual world itself, will end.
So belief in the novel, provisional though it may be, is the condition of
obtaining its particular kind of knowledge. If you don’t commit deeply,
you will not reap the rewards of its vision. It is significant that for the
religious mind knowing also follows belief. The rewards of religious
experience--peace of mind, assurance of salvation, having a divine purpose and
being part of a larger plan and community, even knowing forgiveness--all follow
belief. For, you cannot experience divine forgiveness unless you first
believe in the God who grants it, and in the spiritual condition that demands
it. For the secular, post-Enlightenment mind belief follows knowing.
Secularists place their belief in things that can be verified as a general
rule---the possible versus the impossible. For instance, steady global
rise in temperatures since the 1880’s and the thickness of Greenland’s ice are
scientifically provable measurements that precede belief in global climate
change. While Wood sees the
as if belief of
fiction as secular because it is always something we can refuse at any time, it
is just as possible to see this belief as sharing something elementary with
religious belief. It retains the paradigm of religious seeking (belief
before knowing) rather than of secular skepticism (knowing before belief).
It is
like
religious belief because that investment in the world of a novel is an act of
faith. It is akin to the novelist’s act of faith in the creative process
that brought about the work’s completion.
If you discuss books much over a period of years, you will no doubt observe
that many fundamentalist religious believers as well a growing majority of
secularists share a preference for non-fiction and a general dislike for the
project of fiction, and share, coming from very different points of view, a
strong disapproval of what, for them, is not fact-based. (Non-fiction far
outsells fiction; information now trumps the metaphor). For hard secularists
that would include all forms of superstition including religion, magic, folk
wisdom with no scientific basis and all supernatural occurrences. For
religious fundamentalists that would include the theory of evolution, atheism,
alternative origin narratives to the Biblical account, and all forms of magic
that compete or obviate the need for God. You can easily see how fiction is
suspect, at best an irrelevant game, to these minds that are nourished by the
perceived facts of their world views regardless if their outlook is secular or
religious. For religionists, fiction is too worldly to be trusted, an
idolatrous competitor with the Bible for its hold on the human imagination.
No less a novelist than Tolstoy came to view his own earlier fiction as too
worldly. While the real sticking point with secular post-modern writers
and readers, is that fiction is actually too much like religion as it is
traditionally practiced and appreciated. For, whether a novel is magical
or strictly realistic is almost beside the point. The objection to
fiction may lie in the paradigm of religious seeking (belief before knowing)
represented by traditional fiction. The notion of trusting the creative
process, the subconscious, is too mystical for many writers of serious fiction
today, as is the notion too binding that as readers they are subject to a system
of belief at all (either Wood’s notion or Coleridge’s idea), and must submit to
the novel. Notwithstanding the wide-ranging particulars of modern literary
theory, the entire project might well be summed up as an attempt to strip
fiction of every vestige of religious supplication and transcendence, by
dispelling the notion that we should trust it.
This religious dimension in the novel lies, partly, in the nature and style
of novelistic revelation. It is often intangible, symbolic and elusive.
It works on the reader’s mind in subtle, mysterious ways, through associations,
and recurrent powerful images, much the way images from the prophecies of
Ezekiel, Daniel and Revelation, or the Psalms and parables of Jesus, stay in
our minds and work on our imaginations. The literary style and metaphoric
richness of scripture suggests that a continuation of its literary strategies
exists in the novel, even among the most secular authors. Thus we have
E.M. Forster’s resetting of scriptural quotations in
A Passage to India,
or the retelling of the Cain and Abel story in Steinbeck’s
East of Eden, or
Rushdie’s reinterpretation of Islam and the Koran in
The Satanic Verses to
give just a few of examples of metaphor, content and narrative structure being
borrowed from religious texts. It’s also worth noting that Old Testament
writing, arising often from Pagan source materials, was also borrowed from
earlier literary traditions. These writings may well have begun their
literary journey
as
if before becoming
thus saith the Lord.
That the novel “lives in the shadow of doubt” is an interesting and valid
observation by Wood, but it is one that assumes belief in religious texts, or
religious belief itself, is fundamentally different from our attitudes toward
secular texts. As somebody who was part of a fundamentalist religion for
more than 15 years, I know that the daily life of faith in a supernal reality,
even the grasping of doctrines peculiar to Seventh-Day Adventism on thin
or non-existent scriptural evidence, was far more difficult and doubt filled than the notional
doubt of reading a work of fiction. It was “real” doubt, after all, with a
“real” imperative. As I stated before, if belief in the novel is only
as if, then the
shadow of doubt the novel lives in is also only a provisional shadow. To
live by a fundamentalist paradigm is to inhabit a supernal narrative, a novel,
if you will, wherein you
believe the
highest stakes and gravest consequences may ensue from your decisions and
actions. You ask yourself every day: Am I in the right relationship
with God? Have I acted on God’s principles or on my own selfish desires? Have I
influenced others to do the same? Am I truly saved? Am I
understanding this Bible text correctly? Is the interpretation of
Daniel’s 2300 day prophecy part of a literal time frame? And if a day in
Daniel represents a unit of prophetic time, not a literal day, might a day in
Genesis also represent a non-literal unit of time? On and on the
questions go, sometimes in a confusion of metaphoric and literal readings.
After all, any text, especially a sacred text, which requires our belief, must
in practice exist always under the shadow of doubt. In this way,
religious texts are more closely related to novels than Wood thinks, certainly
more than non-fiction texts. When we are told something is a true story,
we put aside our symbolist and metaphoric (
as if) reading
methods the way we’d take off 3D glasses at the end of a movie.
So (getting back to the real) it seemed, in
Lightbearer, the
best way to present the reality of religious fundamentalists--who believe in
eternal rewards and punishments--to truly understand why fundamentalist
believers sometimes act in ways contradictory to their beliefs (that is, in
inhuman ways) was to present as real the world where god and the devil
literally exist. To dramatize the pressures brought to bear on such
believers and their resulting real world actions. These, after all,
should concern us, Wood as well, more than the effect of Matthew Arnold’s
soft-headed poetry. The “real” necessarily changes in this context.
God becomes real through his followers. So we must believe in him again
for the moment to
understand those followers. Just as accommodating fundamentalist belief
requires our understanding and that dreaded pejorative “tolerance” in life, so
it demands something more of us when we encounter it in a novel. If the
novel is to be more than a form of escape (not only escape into formulaic
fantasies of ourselves but also escape into our dearest ideological
structures), then we must occasionally consent to breathe the same air with the
“other” when it is only the provisional air of a novel. This effort keeps
us honest as pluralists and keeps us from petrifying in our separate ideologies. The
inability to bridge this distance in accessing fiction may reflect a transfer
of rigidity from life to the reading experience, which after all is an
imaginative one. The reach of human understanding, questioning and sympathy, then, is
the ultimate and relevant reality of novels. It is hard to imagine a
secular novel that fails to communicate this pluralism fully in its texts and
to accommodate it in its critical readings.
Even as the Bible’s narrative consistency may collapse under the sustained
assault of literal (realist) interpretations, so faith in God may collapse at
any time in life under the strain of living. The trajectory of this arc
is long and generally stable. I once believed in scripture as God’s Word; I no
longer do and have not for more than 25 years. Was my belief (sustained
for over 15 years)
real
belief if it could collapse? Was it not
provisional after
all? And was not that provisional quality, the thing that could not be
sustained, like a novel that’s premise collapses about half-way through, or the
metaphor that is not sustained or is overworked? In the long view, these
modes of belief Wood dramatically differentiates (actual and metaphoric) are
both subsumed in metaphor, as searches for the right ending that sometimes end
in failure. For, people quit religion and get converted to religion all
the time and often for the same reasons they quit or become obsessed with
reading a certain novel: it is too difficult, they encounter something
with which they disagree, they smell a phony, or they are engrossed by a
genuine vision, understand its deep truths, and are on fire for Bernhard and
God and will soon become their evangelists.
Or, to turn the argument away from the believer toward the object of belief,
we can change the textual dynamics. If a person doesn’t ever believe in
the Bible as divine revelation, then there is only a lifetime’s refusal,
whereas there are thousands and thousands of novels with which a reader may
repeat the process of belief or refusal within a lifetime. If there was
only one novel (say only
Finnegan’s Wake),
then our perspective on the nature of this belief and refusal would be altered
radically. It would either be yea or nay for fiction once and for all based on
that single novel. The monism of the project of fiction then would tend
to freeze or make our view of it absolute. Thus, the multiplicity of
novels (plurality of vision as the core secularity of its form) makes
provisional belief an option in the first place. Hence, if I don’t believe in a
novel about a suicidal fallen angel, I may believe in another novel about a
suicidal housewife in a California suburb, or in one about a suicidal, failed
Austrian pianist.
This multiplicity of texts to choose from gives the reader freedom to
embrace literary visions that suit their sensibilities. As part of this
freedom, the reader retains the final say. For having chosen to believe,
at least enough not to throw the book down in disgust, a reader gets to
interpret the text. In this way, it seems to me, Wood doesn’t follow the
entire cycle of the reader/text loop with sufficient interest. For the
knowledge the novel imparts, the very style and language in which it is
delivered, calls out to be interpreted. It is a major aspect and function
of the novel’s secularity, then, that it is reviewed in secular periodicals and
in universities by a set of literary criteria, not by church synods,
theological tenets and religious forms of critique. A set of assertions
about a work of fiction may be made, but they do not require a profession of belief, or form a creed Although a process of debate exists over religious interpretations, the interpreters of fiction are less likely to view theirs as either moral or life and death matters.
Keeping in mind the generic distrust of fiction I mentioned before, which
either the secular or religious reader may bring to a text, we must consider in
this interpretive process the way fundamental orthodoxies may be superimposed
upon the reception of a novel for the individual and in the literary world as
well, beyond Wood’s notion of provisional belief transpiring in the cozy chair
between the reader and the text (Wood’s theories about fiction are often as
personal as his readings).
Belief does not happen, though, in a vacuum. It is certainly not
as pure or private as Wood’s elevated rhetoric in
The Broken Estate
makes it sound. For, it is rare that an individual reader comes to a text
before it has already been vetted and evaluated by critics like Wood.
Thus readers absorb some snippets on the book jacket, at the very least, that
begin shaping their belief before they even open the book. I would grant that
this mode of belief Wood describes is real and operative for the reader, of
course, whether or not that belief has been influenced beforehand. Yet,
because the process of literary reception is a likely influence on the reader’s
potential belief in the text, because the reader’s evaluation is often
derivative of other readings, and other ideologies in the reader may be present
to influence “belief” in a text, it is not certain that this “provisional”
belief always bears the stamp of secularity.
More specifically, novels of the academy, those written to theory (Pynchon,
DeLillo, Wallace, Rushdie, and Zadie Smith come to mind) will predictably find
“believers” among those who espouse those theories (mainly other writers,
critics and readers within the academy), and “refusers”among those in the
mainstream, who, at the least, have differing notions about narrative form if
not about the world. That is to say, whether a work of fiction is embraced
or dismissed is increasingly defined by ideological agreement or disagreement
with a given text, and thus may be ruptured before the reader begins, or at
least as soon as an ideology is identified in the text by the reader. As
such, an ideological mode of belief is setting in, which again may pre-empt
Wood’s literary notion of belief by privileging novels that present favored
ideologies. Since many of our serious writers and their critics are
housed in the same academic institutions, there is a professional incentive to
cooperate, as well as a built in knowledge of what kinds of novels get noticed
in those circles.
Here is William Gass in a 1978 interview on the subject:
"…increasingly
he writes books that will teach well, you know. He may be teaching books himself. He is often in classes talking
about how you write, to writing
students; before you know it, his books are about writing, and they teach splendidly because you
have all these things that you can do in the class, to point out this device, that
move, and so on…So there is an interaction: the writer is writing, of course,
for the audience he has; the audience he has is also moulded by the kind of books he writes."
Wood is certainly familiar with the dynamic. He has been attacked and
caricatured as a reactionary critic stuck in 19
thcentury realism,
and, not surprisingly, as having reactionary political views as well based on
his critique of much contemporary, post-modern writing, which he famously
described as hysterical realism. In his fascinating study “Practicing
Post-Modernism: The Example of John Hawkes” (Contemporary Literature -
Spring 1991), John M. Unsworth describes the way the language of Hawkes
critical representations of his own works via his interviews migrates directly
to later critical response to his works. In this way, Hawkes (his
example followed by other post-modern practitioners like DeLillo also via
interviews and Thomas Bernhard via his two volume autobiography) orchestrated
reception of his work by acting as first reader. In addition, the
original critical representations of Hawkes work arose from Albert Guerard, the
influential critic who promoted and first brought attention to Hawkes in
1947. In the process, Hawkes was co-opted by Guerard in that his own
representations derive from his mentor (critical praise that may have been
conditional on Hawkes continuing to write in his early “approved” style) and
Hawkes, using his own status and prestige, co-opted his critics by providing
circumscribed interpretations of his works through his interviews.
This practice was already a generation old when Unsworth wrote about it, but is
certainly more entrenched now. Little wonder Wood was attacked for going
off script. You could not miss that Zadie Smith’s critique of Joseph
O’Neill’s
Netherland
(among Wood’s favorite books of 2008) was aimed in part at Wood—a delayed but
sharp literary backhand return of Wood’s devastating serve in his famous
“Human, All too Inhuman”essay. That the novel in the academy has become
ideological along theoretical and professional lines is evident in the way
Wood’s critique was interpreted and decried as a reactionary political attack.
It is hard to see it as any less than an admission of ideological entrenchment
when you respond to your critics: ‘if you don’t like this novel you must be
against its ideology.’
According to Unsworth, "...to date, much of the criticism of
post-modern fiction has...aimed at reproducing the ideology of the fiction it
discusses...The problem...is only exacerbated when author and critic are
contemporaries cohabiting in one institution. Under these circumstances,
the material inducements to cooperation may well subvert the independence of
both parties..." If the compromise of an independent literature
(meaning both authors and their critics) is not concern enough, Unsworth sees
another long term consequence of this kind of critical orchestration and
co-optation within the academy: its potential to freeze future interpretations
of a work and identify it too narrowly with theory such that it will cease to
be read once that theory becomes dated. In the meantime, these works
become engines of theoretical expectation, rather than avant garde novelty.
Such certitude undermines the real risk undertaken by all good fiction, the
process of difficult persuasion, without which the only affirmation possible is
the ‘Yes!’ of the true believer.